Monday, November 18, 2013

Roughest Draft of Critical Photo Essay

This is rough, lacking in all of my images, but it's what I have so far. The synthesis is even fucked, but here:


Like Anne Frances Wysocki, I will follow the conceptualization of visual interaction from Imannuel Kant to the present, but I will not stop at Wysocki. I hope to use Wysocki as a launching point through which I can examine and reveal the masculine and feminine power dynamics underlying values of visual interaction. According to Kant, “That is beautiful which pleases universally” (422). Kant’s endeavor for delineating a universal standard of beauty obviously has its merits, but it assumes an essential quality that inheres in an image. It has become increasingly evident that images in and of themselves cannot contain an essential nature that is accessible to human perception. Though they may contain a true and essential nature, we cannot discover that quality because we are limited to mediating that “discovery” through our limited human faculty. To discover what is essential in an object then is to necessarily taint and shape that discovery. The problem is exacerbated upon considering the loss of individuality.

Though we may at times wish to be considered individual and omnipotent in our constructions of self, there is no denying that each individual arises within a social context that shapes him or her. That shaping, that social construction, brings to bear on everything we perceive. Things have meaning insofar as we have been developed to construct that meaning from the social conditions in which we are constructed. Furthermore, those social relations are dynamic and perpetually subject to change. This too presents a problem to a universal standard by which we interact with images.      

The universal approach to image interaction presupposes a static universe, which is evidently not the case at all. The world might instead be viewed as an amorphous mass, one that is in a constant state of flux. There are constantly shifting social relations and values that simply do not allow for a universal standard of image interaction. So how does visual interaction with images proceed? And how do these interactions shape the visual produced and the viewer of the visual? I intend to outline the current state of theory regarding visual interaction with texts and gain insight into how visual interaction functions not only to shape images, but to shape the viewers who produce those images.

The current state of visual interaction seems to be separated into two opposing schools of thought. These schools of thought are summed up in Anne Frances Wysocki’s “The Sticky Embrace of Beauty.” Wysocki makes the distinction between visual text interactions that favor discovery and ones that favor construction: “they propose that the work of shaping texts visually is to result in objects that stop and hold sight; I would rather that what we make when we shape the visual aspects of texts is reciprocal communication” (149). Herein lies the dichotomy between visual interaction that presupposes decipherment of essential meaning and visual interaction that presupposes construction of meaning. While the balance seems to be shifting toward the latter strategy, approaches to visual interaction continue to endorse the former strategy in turn denying the shift.

Wysocki recognizes this in the tendency of theorists of visual design to establish principles of visual interaction. She uses Robin Williams as an example. Wysocki argues that Williams’s design principles—contrast, repetition, alignments, and proximity— are stated in such a way that they have the appearance of being “not contingent, that they are neutral in their effects—that they have no effects other than the creation of organized layout—, that they should apply anywhere at all times, that they are not values” (151). In a similar manner, Stephen A. Bernhardt presents principles that fail to call attention to their contingent nature.

In “Seeing the Text,” Bernhardt proposes the sort of visual text interaction that Wysocki denounces. Though his intent is to demonstrate how “a preoccupation with conventional essay format allows little attention to visual features” (77 Bernhardt), he promotes a conventionalized visual text interaction. The conventions he endorses are the laws of gestalt—equilibrium, good continuation, closure, and similarities. Stephanie Sabar, in her essay “What’s a Gestalt?” defines gestalt as

an attribute of a perception or a thing that has a quality that is different from (not more than) the sum of its components, the components being the stimuli received from the outside world. It is a quality of the entity as a whole, resulting from its configuration, i.e., the relationship, interaction, and interdependence between its parts, rather than the sum or random combination of its parts (9)

Here I will explain my skepticism and aversion to the “laws” of this theory of perceptual organization.

The first law, the law of equilibrium, is erroneous in its objective grounding as a principle in the very definition Bernhardt provides: “the most relevant law is that of equilibrium, or pragnanz, which suggests that items in a visual field strive for balance or equilibrium with other items in the field (71). The definition personifies the elements in the field of vision such that they are understood as seeking balance. The inclination for balance is rather in the subject viewing the image; these elements are not autonomous, but acted upon by the viewer.

The next law, the law of good continuation, “suggests that visual perception works to pull figures out of the background, to give them definition against the undistinguished field with which they are located” (72), recognizing the role of human perceptual interaction to a certain extent. However, it should be evident that the distinction between figure and background does not inhere in the image. On a 2 dimensional surface, the “undistinguished field” might be just as much figure as the “figure” the law purports to give definition to. The “background” might be considered as the distinguished figure. Why this is not so in many cases is something that can hopefully be reconciled later in this analysis.

 

The third law, the law of similarity functions to impose similarity where similarity might not actually exist. This too is a human construct. This law suggests “that units which resemble each other in shape, size, color, or direction will be seen together as homogeneous grouping” (72). This tendency to make that which is dissimilar similar hinges on organization structure inherent in the human condition. According to Friedrich Nietzsche, “we possess only metaphors of things which in no way correspond to the original entities” (767). This is due to the process through which we designate objects with words. In doing this we erase differences through homogenization induced by conferring on the non-equivalent a characteristic of equivalence through the concepts we attribute to distinct objects: “Every concept comes into being by making equivalent that which is non-equivalent” (Nietzsche 767). For example, every raisin is unique, varying in size and pattern of convoluted folds, but we impose the idea of raisin-ness on each individual raisin and render them similar. In visual textual interaction, the similarity is forced on the elements in a similar matter. While the law of similarity helps to organize a text, I am naturally hesitant of a law that promotes similarity while erasing difference. The differences of the apparently similar elements should be able to call themselves into question.                

The final law, the law of closure, though it has its own flaws, begins to recognize the human role in shaping the visual text. According to the law of closure, “When good continuation or good figure is not provided by the visual stimulus, the perceiver has a tendency to fill in the missing gaps, to provide the missing definition” (Bernhardt 72). This, of course, presumes that there is such thing as a self-contained visual text, that in the case that the visual text is not, the missing gaps and definitions will be apparent enough to be identified. My questions is “What visual text doesn’t contain gaps?” My concern is that by assuming a visual text can be self-contained, we perpetuate the idea of a naturalized text. Regardless of good continuation, every text should be considered as lacking closure. In considering text as such, we might begin to dismantle the naturalized visual text, and make possible the sort of reciprocal communication for which Wysocki calls.

Gestalt theory as enumerated by Bernhardt in 1986 is radically different from current understandings of gestalt (This alone is evidence of shifting beliefs and values). Gestalt theory now holds that “[w]e do not see the world objectively” (Sabar 8), that “what people see is not simply a replica of what is before them” (Sabar 19). Instead, “what we see is interpreted and given meaning by the observer, based on memories, expectations, beliefs, values, fears, assumptions, emotional states, and more” (Sabar 8). The enumeration of factors that control interpretation and give meaning arise out of social relations and experiences with the world. The aforementioned laws of gestalt might be considered amongst these factors, but they are not laws that exist outside of human perception; they are inseparable from learned social values. The visual text necessarily involves construction of meaning, but it does not follow a one-sided construction process. Sabar explains that “one’s existing mind-set shapes a perception or experience as much as the external stimulus affects the mind” (19). The latter part calls attention to the visual texts capability of shaping the viewer, a concern that Wysocki voices in “The Multiple Media of Texts: How Onscreen and Paper Texts Incorporate Words, Images, and Other Media”: “But what might be the consequences of design that ask me to use it unquestioningly, to acquire through what I see and do the values of efficiency and transparency?” (158).

If a consequence of a visual text is to shape the viewer, the acquisition of these values—transparency and efficiency—might be of lesser concern than other values one might subliminally acquire. So far I have discussed two dominant schools of thought regarding visual interaction, but I have failed to call attention to these strategies for visual interaction being gendered. The gendering of visual interaction, and how the values inherent in that gendering shape the viewer are the values I referred to previously as cause for concern.

As Wysocki so aptly puts it in “The Sticky Embrace of Beauty,” the values with which we interact with a text have predominately arisen out of male-controlled discourse in a patriarchal society. She refers back to Kant, stating that his “sense of the world and its functioning grew out of his ability as a man of his time and place to look upon his experiences as being, necessarily, the experiences of all others” (164). This statement at once recognizes the social relations that allow for value-making, but it suggests that the approach is primarily a masculine one. This masculine approach considers beauty as a universal quality inherent in the object/image. Consequently, the power dynamics implicit in Kant’s critique of judgment are effaced. The power that determines beauty is misplaced, removed from the viewer and instead said to arise out of the object. This is not so, however. The implications of Kant’s argument become all the more important when considered against Laura Mulvey’s reckoning of the function of gaze in her essay “Visual Pleasure and Narrative Cinema.”

In her essay, Mulvey argues that gazing is a masculine role and to be gazed upon is a feminine one. The object of gaze is always feminized, always determined to be such by a masculine gazer. According to Mulvey, “In world ordered by sexual imbalance, pleasure in looking has been split between active/male and passive/female. The determining male gaze projects its fantasy onto the female figure, which is styled accordingly” (2088). The visual text then might be considered as feminized, on object to be gazed upon by masculine power and determined to be beautiful, or not beautiful, by masculine judgment. Kant’s argument can then be understood as rendering the gazed-upon as an object disembodied. The function of this visual interaction promotes the gender disparity that benefited Kant. A female adopting the masculine role as gazer would twice conform to masculine ideology by uncritically accepting Kant’s critique of judgment: “The actual image of woman as (passive) raw material for the (active) gaze of man takes the argument a step further into the content and structure of representation, adding a further layer of ideological significance demanded by the patriarchal order” (2094). If the content and structure of representation are male-dominated and the gazed-upon is feminine, the adoption of Kant’s particular ideology is utterly disempowering to females.

            This power structure produces circumstances in which feminine empowerment arises out of embracing the masculinized role as gazer so that power for females is permitted only insofar as the power is mediated through patriarchal ideology. In a BBC televisions series with John Berger, Berger states the following:

Men act and women appear. Men look at women. Women watch themselves being looked at. This determines not only most relations between men and women but also the relation of women to themselves. The surveyor of women in herself is male: the surveyed female. Thus she turns herself into an object—and most particularly an object of vision: a sight” ()

Through their function as masculine gazer, females even objectify themselves. Upon viewing themselves as “objects that stop and hold sight” (Wysocki 149), objects for which they have no role in the determination of beauty, their autonomy is rendered useless. They are powerless in a system that perpetually endorses active masculine agency and passive feminine objects. If what Wysocki suggests—when “we see what does not have beauty as an apparently inherent quality and does not therefore live up to our formal expectations, we denigrate it, or try to lay (or force) perfect form upon it, or we try to erase it” (168)—is true, then females run the risk of self-effacement by failing to subvert masculine principles of visual interaction.

            The issue concerning theories of visual interaction is then much greater than it appears superficially. Wysocki calls for a visual interaction that involves “reciprocal communications, shaping both composer and reader and establishing relationships among them” (173), but no matter the form of interaction, if it continues to be backed by masculine ideology, the position remains the same for females. The values that we carry with us to the visual interaction continue to arise out of a patriarchal hegemony, so they fail to resolve gender disparity. Her suggestion might be understood as the masculine gazer controlling and shaping the object gazed upon. Though a relationship does develop, it is still a relationship of inequity because the values residing in the viewer emanate from the hegemonic structure that shapes the viewer. The real issue is the structure that shapes values. The other issues is that Wysocki’s argument demands what already exists. What Wysocki calls for is recognition of how we actually already perceive things.

            Visual perception proceeds in such a way that much of what is perceived is imposed on the scene by the viewer.  According to Aude Oliva, a principle research scientist at MIT, “viewing a scene is an active process in which perceived images are combined with stored knowledge to create an internal reconstruction of the visual world… The visual features extracted from the image (e.g., color, lines, and patterns of texture) are rearranged according to our expectations and knowledge of the world” (Oliva). The shaping of the text is already a process through which we inevitably interact with visuals. We bring our expectations, values, and all that is stored in our minds to create a scene that is uniquely our own. The creators of the visual text do the same thing in producing the visually interactive text. There is no fidelity between the image intended and the image perceived. Whether one recognizes interpretation of visual text as contingent on values or not, it is already happening through the way our brains process images. Consider the following picture:

How one interprets the image depends on the meaning one places in eagles and a man chained to a rock in a barren land. An American initiated into knowledge of the eagle representing freedom and American patriotism might read the message as anti-terrorist. The man chained to the rocks then might be interpreted as a man bound by his amoral heathen ideology in the desolate Middle East with the symbol of America reigning over him. This, of course, is a painting of Prometheus, which I know because I’ve conducted research on the mythological archetype. The point here, though, is that my knowledge of what this image is intended to represent is irrelevant. No matter what knowledge one brings to the visual text interaction, that knowledge will shape the nature of the interpretation.    

With this understanding visual interaction, it seems interpretation doesn’t just vary across people, time, and culture, but can vary across an individual as well, depending on his or her particular affordances at a given time. Endeavors to find universal principles underlying visual interaction and even ones that seek value-contingent principles are futile attempts to impose order on what is inherently chaotic. There is really no tracing the myriad factors that lend themselves to each individual’s visual interaction on a micro-level, but this is not to say that amendments to visual interaction should be abandoned.

If we understand theories of visual interaction as a structure that reinforces power disparity between males and females and continuously objectifies women, we should alter the features of visual communication. However, the solution to gender inequity relies not on recognition of value contingency, but rather on re-examining the power structures that shape those values. I’m not calling for a radical revamping of patriarchal society. That seems incredibly unrealistic. But maybe I should be.   
 

No comments:

Post a Comment